The exercise of moral, social or civic responsibility is desirable and should be encouraged. So long as the call to act responsibly is not used as an excuse for discouraging protest or as a means of requiring moral or social conformity, such encouragement is socially valuable. But, I wish to argue, it should not be offered in the name of citizenship.
We often describe moral or social responsibility in terms of citizenship, and we talk freely about the rights and responsibilities of citizens. I want to challenge this language. We should, in my view, separate citizenship from assertions or claims about values or standards of conduct. We should recognise that citizenship is a legal status, and put this in a separate category from claims about types of person.
To associate responsibility with citizenship is to assume that citizenship is, at least ideally, virtuous. This assumption implies that holding citizenship creates or encourages virtue in the individual, and that we as a society should be safer among citizens than among aliens, or non-citizens.
Advertisement
However, for all the talk of the value and importance of citizenship in generating feelings of community and attachment to others, citizenship does not guarantee responsibility.
One of the most disturbing aspects of the London bombings in July 2005 was that the majority of the perpetrators were British citizens - not just naturalised, but citizens by birth. If the assumption that citizenship is associated with responsibility is accurate, these people should have felt responsibility towards the community of their birth and nationality. But they did not. Their sense of identity, loyalty and purpose lay elsewhere.
We might deplore this, but we have to recognise the reality. Being a citizen does not necessarily make you a good person.
The converse provides another reason for separating responsibility from the language of citizenship. Being a non-citizen does not make you a bad person. When we prioritise citizenship in our language, by tying words like responsibility and citizenship together in the same sentence or under the same title, we imply that there is something inherently less virtuous in non-citizens, something even potentially suspect about them.
This is particularly disturbing, even dangerous at present, because of the tendency of government and the public to be suspicious of “non-Australians”, and to doubt the moral and social commitments of non-citizens or aliens.
The Cronulla riots late last year were interpreted in that light by many, as a conflict of Australians v “ethnics”, citizens v non-citizens, insiders v outsiders. Language that assumes an association between responsibility and citizenship encourages this sort of thinking. The reality is that, just as citizens might engage in morally irresponsible, even socially destructive acts, aliens or non-citizens can be socially virtuous. Permanent residents in Australia invariably live lives that are, in terms of moral or civic responsibility, indistinguishable from those of legal citizens.
Advertisement
Another reason for separating responsibility or virtue from our thinking about citizenship is that is assumes that all citizens are able to perform positive acts of moral or social responsibility. Indeed, it suggests that they should be required to act in such a way, in order to be true citizens.
Of course, certain legal duties - placing one’s name on the electoral roll, voting, and performing jury duty - are required of citizens. It is also often said that citizens must obey the laws and pay taxes. But all people in the country, even only temporarily, must obey the law, and all who earn an income must pay taxes, whether or not they are citizens.
Everyone, regardless of their nationality, should act decently and thoughtfully towards others. But to require anything more of citizens in the name of moral or social responsibility is to create inequities.
There are many citizens whose capacities are limited, or whose lives are already over-burdened. For one reason or another, many people find just getting through the day to be an ordeal. We add an extra burden to their lives if we castigate them for failure to take part in extra activities that we assume to be the responsibility of citizens.
Just as this assumes too much of all citizens, it also diverts attention from the responsibility that should be demanded of others - non-citizens, governments, and corporations. We sometimes talk of “corporate citizenship” but corporations are not citizens. They should not, however, be let off the hook of exercising responsibility, any more than governments should - not as a moral attribute of citizenship, but as a requirement of law and democracy.
In conclusion, we should talk about moral or social responsibility more generally, and we should liberate it from talk about citizenship.
We should recognise that citizenship, in itself, does not make a person virtuous, and that being a non-citizen does not, in itself, make a person morally suspect.
If citizens speak out in support of terrorism, for example, what is unacceptable is not the fact that they are speaking as citizens. It is not like failing to support your country’s football team! What is unacceptable is the fact that they are supporting a destructive and nihilistic act. When non-citizens speak in support of terrorism, what is deplorable is not that they are doing this as non-citizens but, again, as supporters of such an act.
Whether we intend it or not, we reinforce a sense of alienation and undermine the sense of community we want to create if we talk in ways that divide people, categorising them as insiders and outsiders, rather than stressing our commonalities as people.
When we assume that citizenship carries with it a code of moral or social conduct, we do a disservice to virtuous non-citizens and we also blind ourselves to the causes of destructive and anti-social behaviour. The absence of citizenship does not cause it, and citizenship will not solve it.