There is more than enough ethical mud in genetics of 1998 to keep physicians, lawyers, scientists and bioethicists on guard. A majority are unaware of the progress made in routine and exotic genetics, and most are caught off guard by each
new technology. At the same time, in the United States most scientists receive no more than a few hours’ training in ethics, most physicians take no training in genetics, and it was revealed in 1997 that less than 16% of those who received a
prominent genetic test for susceptibility to cancer were counseled about the choice. The first time most families in the West learn about the practical issues in genetic testing is when a friend or relative needs a test urgently during pregnancy.
To make matters worse, apart from bioethics conferences there is still virtually no common public or scientific international conversation about gene therapy, reproductive rights, or genetic patenting.
Costs of genetic services will fall precipitously just as evidence accumulates about the costs associated with having particular genes. Virtually every culture will have to cope with an unparalleled pressure to conserve social resources by
applying pressure to individuals in an attempt to modify their reproductive behavior and other life choices.
Bioethics and resource allocation
Advertisement
Bioethics is only 40 years old! Much has been discussed and written about the ethics of equity especially Utilitarianism and Consequentialist derivatives of it. Rawls’ concepts of distributive justice have been important here as well,
interpreted by Norman Daniels, as have the economics of efficiency and their respective applications to how best to match limited resources to demand. These ethical and economic notions – of equity and efficiency - in turn stimulated health
services research and technology assessment as research methods. The intention was to provide better quality data relating to effectiveness, side effects, and cost of treatment. This was one of the drivers behind the evidence-based medicine
movement of the past decade.
The debate has broadened well beyond professional and political boundaries. Through the connectivity of information technology (not just the web and associated nets), it has engaged broad community interest in the relation of breakthroughs to
rationing. Public opinion in Australia remains firmly wedded to universal health insurance as the dominant method of payment for health care. This derives in part from an appreciation that illness and injury remain largely capricious and that
there is a need to distribute the high costs of effective health care across a wide community base.
In a sense, therefore, we have been primed to contemplate the impact of the human genome project, post-genome technology roll-out and all the attendant and derivative technologies within an ethical and economic context. Featuring in the
discourse with stronger valence than previously are the interests of commerce.
Questions that loom large
The questions that might be asked in our discussion about resource allocation for the future have more to do with the relation of therapeutic commercial and industrial development and the style of society in which we live than about genetics
itself. Many of these questions are pre-figured in our current concern with multinational commercial hegemony. Multinationals exert great pressure on countries, especially those in the Anglophone democratic world where governments have downsized
and rolled over in near surrender and abandoned the welfare state (Cass, 1999). Eschewing dependence and powerlessness among their people, they have set out to become dependent and powerless themselves by abdication to the market. And the market
is precisely where gene technology is to be found. ‘The human genome project will provide enormous commercial opportunities for the pharmaceutical and biotechnology industries, which have been quick to realise the potential for new treatments…there
is growing excitement in pharmaceutical circles that the genome project may identify new genes and proteins that have a role in disease’ (Savill 1997, pg 44). However, with this will come huge risks. If biotechnology is the commercial rage of
the next age of therapeutics, and genetically modified food producers are to call the shots in world agripolicy, we have worries in store that are only hinted at in our current ethical debates.
Let us assume that genetic interventions with preventive or therapeutic value do emerge and that gene therapy (at which there have already been many thousands of attempts) becomes an effective addition to the therapeutic armamentarium. The
likelihood is that this will be commercially led. The commerce of these developments is foreshadowed in aphorisms such as ‘biotech is as big as the IT revolution’. It will be driven by commercial values. Products will follow that are either
desperately expensive for the few (if the market is small) or focussed on disease of high frequency only among those communities that could afford to pay for them (hypertension rather than malaria). Where, pray tell, in all of this is poor old
‘equity’? The time is now to begin the complex but essential health economic/health ethical discussion lest the north-south divide is further widened, all in the name of genomic science and its boisterous progeny, genetic-based prevention and
therapy.
Advertisement
Jeffrey Sachs, director of the Centre for International Development and professor of international trade at Harvard University, wrote last year of the north-south divide in The Economist. 'Just as knowledge is becoming the undisputed
centrepiece of global prosperity (and lack of it, the core of human impoverishment), the global regime on intellectual property rights requires a new look...now transnational corporations and rich-country institutions are patenting everything
from the human genome to rainforest biodiversity. The poor will be ripped off unless some sense and equity are introduced into this runaway process' (1999, pg 20).
To summarise, the mapping of the human genome will release intense commercial energy. This will pose huge problems about access to new therapies, which will inevitably be expensive. Only the new slaves, the normal, ever-more-working workers,
will be able to pay.
Gene technology applied to food crop development has been heavily entrepreneurial, in many instances disrespectful if not arrogant, in relation to long-term human and environmental consequences. It does not bode well for future cut-throat
commericalisation of gene-based technologies directed toward disease prevention and cure. The public-commercial interactions may not evolve favourably for those who value equity.
This paper was originally presented at the University of Sydney's Templeton Workshop 2000. The author wishes to acknowledge the assistance of Amanda Dominello in preparing this paper.