By definition, the climate is the long term average of the weather. But we also think of the climate as the collection of natural forces (sea surface temperatures, wind circulation patterns, humidity etc) which causes (and thus explains) the weather we have.
If over a period of some years the weather changes from what it has previously been, becoming hotter, say, or wetter, or even more varied, by definition the climate has changed. We should have no more trouble in saying this than we do in saying that if our batswoman's performance changes, then so does her form.
Similarly if the weather changes in some particular way that shows a definite trend, we should not have any trouble in saying this is caused by a change in the climate.
Advertisement
Of course, just as our batswoman can get out early to an unplayable ball without being judged to be in poor form, so too can an unusual weather event be put down to chance rather than a change in the climate. But when the average starts to shift, we will happily use that changed average in cricket to explain changed future performance, and we should have no more difficulty in explaining a trend in the weather by reference to a change in the climate.
In short, what we learn from cricket here is that we have a pretty good understanding of the relationship between observed performance and theorised underling causal abilities, even when the relationship between the two allows a probability of unexpected events, and we can apply this understanding to the relationship between the weather and the climate. Thus we should have no more reason to reject a change in the climate as an explanation for changed weather than we have to reject a change in form as an explanation for changed batting performance.
Cricket is no less helpful in thinking about the role of peer review in science. Peer review plays the same role in science as the selectors play in cricket.
The role of the selectors is to consider candidates for the team, and reject those whom they think will be most easily beaten by the opposition teams to be played. Selection certainly does not guarantee that the chosen players will be successful, but no one expects this. If someone were to say that probably every team member chosen by the selectors will be beaten by an opposition team at some stage, we would all respond with a 'so what' rather than shock. What would shock us would be evidence that the selectors used some criterion other than their assessment of the players' likely success in choosing the team.
We would defend the role of the selectors not on the basis that their choosing a player was sufficient to ensure that they would be successful, but rather that choosing some players rather than others is necessary to having a team which might win and indeed to having a team at all. For if there were no selectors, anyone could roll up to the ground and claim to be playing for Australia. Perhaps the women's team, tired of being sent to the Bankstown oval, might run on the SCG to face the glory of English manhood in the battle for the ashes – or if the English had given up on selectors too, perhaps our women's team would face the Barmy Army. Indeed, why not go further and dispense with the teams entirely and just have the crowd bring their own bats and balls and play as they wish?
Clearly doing away with the selectors could lead to a lot of fun, but it will not allow us to decide who gets to keep the ashes.
Advertisement
We have no difficulty in appreciating the role of the selectors as necessary but not sufficient for choosing a successful national cricket team – male or female – even though we might disagree with their decisions on occasions. Certainly we do not take as a reason to give up on the process the claim that on average less than half the teams chosen by selectors will win the game for which they have been chosen – even though this is true. What would persuade us to change the selection system would be evidence that, by its very nature, it was not directed at choosing the best team.
We should have no more difficulty in appreciating the role of peer review. It is certainly not sufficient to ensure the publication of only those papers which will survive criticism for a long time (and thus be practically accepted as true), but it is necessary to ensuring that the contest between claims is restricted to those which at least have a chance of success. What would persuade us to change the system of peer review would be evidence that, by its very nature, it was not directed to choosing the papers which are most likely to withstand criticism. But there is no evidence of this in the complaints about the system of scientific selection recently aired here.
Discuss in our Forums
See what other readers are saying about this article!
Click here to read & post comments.
29 posts so far.